For some time I have been considering the thesis that both
historicism and literalism emphasize the historical in such a way that said
emphasis creates a barrier to significance for each, but in different ways. For
this post I will limit my considerations to how this common emphasis is
exemplified within Christianity; however, a similar critique may be applicable
elsewhere.
Two things should be mentioned before we define our terms.
First, I assume both historicism and literalism are employed initially in the
understanding and use of the Christian scriptures. So that will be our primary
focus; nonetheless, the implications of this initial employment spread out into
the various ways the Christian faith is understood and lived.
Also, I assume that these two categories, as we will use
them, are somewhat hyperbolic. By that I mean there will not be a one-for-one
identification of most individuals and/or groups with these categories as we
will define them. Even so these categories, so understood, will help clarify
the issues and potential solutions.
I take historicism to refer to that approach to the
scriptures that emphasizes the historical context of the scriptures in such a
way that any understanding of a given text must be limited to its context and
time.
I take literalism to refer to that approach to the
scriptures that emphasizes the historical nature of the scriptures in such a
way that any understanding of a given text must begin with the belief that said
text corresponds precisely with the historical facts as they occurred.
Already we can see the common emphasis on the historical.
Tracking the history of this common emphasis would be a fruitful endeavor.
Without taking such a route I will simply say that both approaches are the
product of modernity and were not in place prior. That is telling, and one
might look to various approaches to the scriptures prior to the modern era to
see what I intend to show, which is simply that significance (think here: meaning)
trumps historicity. I will not take that approach simply because to do so would
lend more credence to historicity than I intend to give. So let’s take a,
widely speaking, philosophical approach instead.
Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that whatever
truths the historicist or the literalist believes as regards the scriptures are
primarily historical truths. For the historicist this will mean that she
believes certain truths as regards the context and time of the scriptures. She
may or may not also hold as true certain events that are related within the
scriptures. For the literalist this will simply mean he believes whatever is
found in the scriptures in fact happened.
Given this assumption my basic argument is as follows: If
all one believes is that something is historically true, i.e. it happened, then
it does one no good. Said another way: If all I have acquired from a particular
text is a belief that something happened then all I have is a belief that
something happened. This may strike us as an existential tautology of the most
annoying kind, and it is.
What more is needed then? Well, the precise addition to my
historical belief that is needed will be meaning, significance. And this
meaning, this significance, will not ultimately depend on my belief that
something happened. In fact, as I will argue, if I emphasize the priority of my
historical belief, as it were, then that very belief may function as a barrier
to my having significant access to meaning.
The problem here is that meaning, significance, always
transcends the facts. Meaning, qua
meaning, is not a historical fact. This is why the meaning of any given
historical fact will vary depending on the one pronouncing on the historical
fact. All we have to do is gather all the various books that have been written
on the historical Jesus and it will become evident that few, if any of them,
agree as to what his life as historical fact means.
That being said, if the meaning of who Jesus was and what he
did depended on the facts, as we have them, then there should be widespread
agreement as to what that meaning is. But there isn’t such agreement. Hence,
the meaning does not depend on knowing or believing the facts.
That conclusion will strike our modern minds as
counter-intuitive. But, it did not strike the minds of the ancients in that
way. From Origen to Augustine we see a clear recognition that the significance
of Christ could not be gleaned from knowing the facts, much less from simply
believing them.
In fact the scriptures make things quite easy on us by
giving us, in no uncertain terms, the meaning we need. “For God so loved the
world that he gave his only begotten Son, so that everyone who believes in him
may not perish but may have eternal life. Indeed, God did not send the Son into
the world to condemn the world, but in order that the world might be saved
through him” John 3:16-17.
Notice that there is no way we could simply glean this
meaning from the facts, as facts. Why is that? Well, this meaning includes
God’s intentions as well as a clear statement of God’s love. We might happily
guess at such meanings in relation to those facts (that would be highly
unlikely, but a wonderful guess nonetheless), but the facts, qua facts, certainly do not make this
meaning an obvious inference or implication.
In other words, simply knowing the facts (Jesus lived, died,
and rose again) does not communicate to us, in themselves, that we are loved by
God or saved through those events. How could we know such things unless we are
told in so many words: that is what those facts mean? If we were left to our
own resources we would simply end up with any number of books on the historical
Jesus claiming any number of meanings.
This brings us back to the priority of historical emphasis
found in both historicism and literalism. Assuming for the moment the meaning
given above is the intended meaning, how do their respective emphases function
as possible barriers to their having significant access to this meaning?
The problem for the historicist is that any meaning she will
accept will have to be context embedded. So for instance, she will not give
credence to the above meaning as representing in any way God’s intentions or
love. On the contrary, she will see the above meaning as simply the meaning
assumed by the Johannine community and nothing more.
If she takes her historicism seriously, doing so will always
be more than a sufficient defeater for any attempt to believe, based on the
above text, that God in fact does love her. In other words, she may believe God
does love her but it will not be because it says so in John’s gospel. And if
she does believe such, it will always be at risk of believing in spite of
having no good historical reason for doing so.
Moreover, she will assume that she, herself, is so historicized
that any meaning at all is simply to be explained by antecedent historical
facts relative to her and her socio/economic/political context. Sadly, in her
most lucid moments she will readily admit that she believes something at any
time has happened; but she knows not what or what it might mean. Not only does
her historicism function as a barrier to meaning, but also as a barrier to the
very facts she places priority upon.
The problem for the literalist is not as complicated as it
is for the historicist. The problem for the literalist is that he will assume
since he believes Jesus really did die and rise again that he has done all that
is needed. He will have access to the above meaning, but it will be secondary
to his primary belief in the historical fact. This makes things very easy for
the literalist. There is nothing he really needs to do, but believe. In fact he
will easily reduce all of the world's problems and solutions to simply those
who believe the facts and those who don’t.
To say it a little differently, any meaning or significance
for the literalist is settled in his believing the facts. In my humble opinion,
it is this settling of any concern for significance through one’s ability to
believe a historical fact that has created a kind of Christianity in our
culture that has an appearance of power, but is really (sadly) anemic.
What about a solution? At this point the historicist will
assume any solution is so contextually embedded that it will not have any
transcendent value or application. The literalist will simply assume there is
no problem; therefore, no need for a solution. I, obviously enough, disagree.
It seems to me no mistake that having faith is given within the scriptures as the starting point.
And I assume by faith we are not to understand it as referring to mere belief,
but to understand it as an act of trust (which may include belief in some
measure).
But what is it we are to trust? What does it mean to
“believe in him?” Without prolonging this post, I assume we are to trust “him”
as we do a person. Moreover, we are to trust that God loves us, that “in him”
we are not condemned but saved. Now, all of this will require more meaning, and
happily that is given to us as well.
The obvious point here is that people are not facts, in the
strictest sense of the word. It is true that there are facts about people, and
that the notion “a particular person exists” is considered a fact. But, facts
do not have intentions towards us. Facts do not love us.
And so the historicist need not balk at the prospect of
being asked to believe facts that are not clearly given by the context. She is
not asked to trust in facts, but in Someone. And the literalist must not stop
at the facts. He must go further and trust in Someone whose expectations involve
more than mere belief.
As in any relationship, it always takes time for trust to be
established, but once that trust obtains certain facts become known. This is
risky business for sure, but Love always Is.
No comments:
Post a Comment