In his defense of religious exclusivism, Alvin Plantinga
gives a somewhat tangential mention of a phenomenology that attends belief (citation
at end). In this post, I am not interested in speaking to Plantinga’s defense
of exclusivism, but I do want to consider this phenomenology of belief he
mentions. To whit, it seems to me that if we believe something, part of why we
believe that something is because it strikes
us as true. That is, it seems true to us. This phenomenon of seeming true (or,
false, for that matter) is not wholly within our control. Why does that matter?
Well, for me, I have struggled to find ways to clarify my understanding of not
only the experience of belief, but also the humility that it seems should
attend belief. Something Plantinga says in that defense has helped me
understand these better.
So Plantinga: “What is internally available to the believer
also includes the phenomenology that
goes with the beliefs in question; the sensuous
phenomenology but also the nonsensuous phenomenology involved, for example,
in the belief’s just having the feel of being right.”
The reader will have to forgive me for not spending time on
the context of this claim. To do so would be to carry us far away from our
intended target. My sole interest is in considering the nonsensuous phenomenology
of a belief’s having a feel of being
right. I know exactly what Plantinga speaks of here and I have been trying
to say something to that effect for some time.
For example, it is often (very often) the case that I will
hear an argument, or claim, and I will get the sense that something is not
quite right. I can’t put my finger on just what it is, but something doesn’t
feel right. And conversely, I have had the same experience where a claim seems
clearly right, but I have neither a clear understanding nor words for saying
why it seems right. In time, as I wrestle with that claim, it will sometimes
happen that I will come to a clearer understanding of why it had a feel of
being right (or not right-given the case). However, sometimes I just have the
feeling without the clarity.
When I say something doesn’t “feel” right I do not mean
feeling in terms of an emotion, nor even in terms of pain or pleasure. It is
not sensuous in that way. It is
simply a kind of sense that something is right or not quite right-as the case
may be. Of course, in these examples we are thinking of special cases that merely
amplify what is always there. What is always there, phenomenologically speaking, is the
sense that something is or is not right (is true or is not false, good or not good,
etc.).
No matter what it is we believe, we believe it because it
strikes us a true. This seems to be the case whether we have good reasons for
believing it or not. I can be presented with a whole host of reasons for
believing p is true, and yet if p does not strike me as true it will be
of no consequence one way or the other.
We cannot simply decide something is going to
strike us as true, nor can we always predict what it is we will believe. Consider again some proposed truth claim p. As Plantinga might put it, I can try
my level best to believe p. I can
consider all the evidence in regards to p.
I can work my way diligently through all the arguments in favor of p. And yet, in many cases, no one will
be able to know (predict/guess) whether or not the end of these deliberations will result in
my belief that p is true.
I say “in many cases”
because there are some clear exceptions. Clearly the deliverances of
mathematics are an exception. If you do not clearly see that 2+2=4, I will be concerned
that you either have misunderstood what it means or you unfortunately have some
kind of cognitive malfunction. The deliverances of mathematics are the
strongest exceptions. A close runner up would be basic logical principles such
as the law of contradiction.
Also, the deliverances of the various scientific methods are
to be considered exceptions, with a caveat. The obviousness of the deliverances
of the various scientific methods comes by degrees. At one end of the scale
there is something close to obviousness, at the other end we have much room for
disagreement. It should be obvious, all things being equal and understood, that
water is composed of molecules that in turn consist of two hydrogen atoms and a
single oxygen atom. It may not be as obvious that the benefits of drinking
coffee are as such-and-such a study claims. At any rate, in all of these (math,
logic, and the sciences), there will be a good chance of guessing correctly
what my resulting belief will be.
You will probably guess correctly that I will come to the
conclusion that 2+2 in fact equals 4. You will probably guess correctly that I
will conclude that some A cannot be
both A and not-A. And you will probably guess correctly that I will agree that
at sea level water boils at about 212 degrees F (assuming we scientifically
discover this conclusion).
So those are the exceptions. What are not exceptions, by any
stretch of the imagination, are many of the claims that concern ethics,
religion, and other more “philosophical” pursuits. What you and I believe in regards to these is always a matter of debate. You may present
me with some religious claim p and I
can do my level best to believe p,
but you will not be able to predict if such a belief will obtain for me.
In these cases, I will believe p if and only if p
strikes me as true. And, even I will not be able to predict if p will seem true to me. There is a great
mystery to this phenomenon. Let’s assume I do believe p. Even if I can offer reasons for why I believe p, there is still some possible world
where I know those same reasons and yet do not believe p. Belief in p is not
necessary for me.
Again, there is something involved here that is not wholly dependent on me. I cannot just pull myself up by my bootstraps and believe just
any old thing I want to believe. There is an important sense in which we can
say the truth of p happens to me.
This is what makes it phenomenological. There is a phenomenon I can observe
where either p seems true to me or it
doesn’t. I can even observe a change where once I believed p and now I don't. But, what I cannot do is simply manufacture that
change on my own.
This is where humility comes into play. When it comes to
belief there is something that happens to me that I have no control over. It is
true that I can try to believe, but no guarantee I will. If this is the case
for others as it is for me (and we assume it is the case), then humility is in
order. As long as I recognize this phenomenon, then I can expect from others
only what I expect from myself. What I expect from myself is to try my level
best when it comes to these most important matters of religion, ethics, and the
like. I must do my level best to reside in the truth as these matters are
concerned. But I can only believe what seems true to me. You can only believe
what seems true to you. We are the same in this matter even if we disagree.
For the work
mentioned above:
Alvin Plantinga, “A Defense of Religious Exclusivism”; found
in Philosophy of Religion: An anthology, ed.
Louis Pojman and Michael Rea; Wadsworth,;
2012; pp. 646-47.
No comments:
Post a Comment